Robert Piercey
That
Deleuze’s thought is heavily indebted to Spinoza is a claim that is both
obvious and obscure. On the one hand, Deleuze says quite plainly that he is “a
Spinozist,” and that Spinoza is for him “the ‘prince’ of philosophers” [1]. On
the other hand, it is hard to imagine that the thinker of difference and
pre-individual singularities could have anything in common with Spinoza,
thinker of the one absolutely infinite substance and monist par excellence. One might, under the circumstances, be tempted to
divide Deleuze’s books into two groups:those in which he speaks in his own name,such
as Difference and Repetition and The Logic of Sense; and those which deal
with the history of philosophy, such as Expressionism
in Philosophy: Spinoza.
But to
make such a division would be a mistake. Deleuze’s reading of Spinoza, far from
being peripheral to his own thought, is in fact central to it. Indeed, I want
to argue here that Deleuze’s ontology of difference cannot be adequately
understood outside the context of Expressionism
in Philosophy. I intend to show that Difference
and Repetition and The Logic of Sense
are in large part attempts to articulate an expressionistic ontology, and that
they must be read in light of what Deleuze says about expression in his work on
Spinoza. Accordingly, what follows is divided into three parts. The first gives
an overview of Deleuze’s ontology, and shows that it invokes a tripartite
distinction among Being, the virtual, and the actual. Part Two traces this
tripartite scheme back to Deleuze’s reading of Spinoza, and fleshes out
Deleuze’s claim that it is a necessary part of an expressionistic ontology. And
in Part Three, I explain how Deleuze both preserves and modifies the Spinozist
scheme in his own work. In doing so, I try to show that Difference and Repetition and The
Logic of Sense are attempts “to make substance turn around the modes -- in other words, to realize univocity
in the form of repetition” [2].
1. Deleuze as ontologist
It is
often said – indeed, it has become something of a cliché – that Deleuze’s texts
operate on many levels at once. In Constantin Boundas’s apt expression, they
create multiple “series,” series which “converge and become compossible” at the
same time as they “diverge and begin to resonate” [3]. Thus Deleuze’s texts
contain a highly original semantics, and a theory of subjectivity, and certain
views on the relation of philosophy to political practice. It is less commonly
recognized that they contain an ontology – where ‘ontology’ means, roughly,an account
of what there is.But Deleuze’s writings abound with ontological claims. Difference and Repetition describes its
task as the articulation of a “philosophy of ontological difference” (DR, xix). Similarly, The Logic of Sense insists that any
genuinely philosophical inquiry eventually “merges with ontology” [4].
Deleuze’s work of the late 1960s advances an ontology of difference – that is,
a metaphysics in which differentiation and determination are seen as the
principal characteristics of what there is.
At the
same time, Deleuze’s ontology is a kind of transcendental philosophy [5]. His
ontological claims emerge from something like transcendental analysis, in that
they describe “not the sensible, but the being of the sensible” (DR, 266). They are a “transcendental
empiricism” (DR, 56) – “empiricism”
because their subject matter is something “which can be perceived only from the
standpoint of a transcendental sensibility”
(DR, 144) [6], “transcendental”
because they describe not the material world itself, but the conditions of
there being such a world. Deleuze’s ontology seeks “to determine an impersonal
and pre-individual transcendental field, which does not resemble the
corresponding empirical field” (LS,
102), but which makes the empirical field possible.
The
notion of a “field,” then, is central to Deleuze’s ontology [7]. Deleuze not
only talks about a “pre-individual transcendental
field;” he distinguishes three fields
in his ontological writings. Now, to say that Deleuze distinguishes three
ontological fields is merely to say that he makes three different types of
ontological claim. It is also to say that claims referring to one field have a
different status than those referring to another – that claims about (say) the
material field are fundamentally different from ones about a transcendental
field. But it is not to say that the two sets of claims concern different
worlds. It is not to say that in addition to the empirical world, there is
another actual realm which transcends
it or from which it emanates.To distinguish fields as Deleuze does is just to
say that different kinds of ontological claim are formally distinct. A familiar
example of a formal distinction in ontology is Heidegger’s insistence that the Seinsfrage is fundamentally different
from questions about entities. To the extent that this is so, Being and
entities belong to different ontological fields. Another example – and one
Deleuze incorporates into his own work – is Duns Scotus’s theory of virtual
descriptions. Scotus maintains that some of a material entity’s properties are
virtual. They genuinely bvelong to the entity, but do not correspond to any of
its material features. “Unity” is an example of a virtual property. Every
entity is unified, so unity may be truly predicated of any object; but we cannot
sense an object’s unity as we can sense (say) its colour. Virtual properties
are indeed properties, but they cannot be isolated in the material world. They
are real but not actual. While they do not belong to the same ontological field
as material properties, neither do they pertain to an extra-material world.
Talk about the virtual is simply a different way of describing the one world.
Similarly, Deleuze’s talk about fields is a way of keeping apart formally
distinct types of ontological claim, without suggesting that they describe
different worlds. But what are the fields he has in mind?
Difference and Repetition invokes three fields.
The ontology put forward here consists of a tripartite scheme: two types of
“repetition,” and the “difference” that lies between them. This scheme, Deleuze
argues, is implicit in even the simplest attempt to explain what “repetition”
means. We naturally think of repetition as “difference without concept” – that
is, as what appears “when we find ourselves confronted by identical elements
with exactly the same concept” (DR,
23), such as different drops of water. But how is such repetition possible?
What must we presuppose in order for non-conceptual difference to occur? The
answer, Deleuze claims, is that this “bare, material repetition (repetition of
the Same) appears only in the sense that another repetition is disguised within
it, constituting it and constituting itself” (DR, 21). This is the “secret subject” of repetition, a repetition
that “unfolds as pure movement” (DR,
24). Whatever this “more profound” repetition is, Deleuze urges that it not be
confused with the “bare, material” kind – that is, with what goes on in the
empirical world. He writes:
We are right to speak
of repetition when we find ourselves confronted by identical elements with
exactly the same concept. However, we must distinguish between these discrete
elements, these repeated objects, and a secret subject, the real subject of
repetition, which repeats itself through them. Repetition must be understood in
the pronominal. (DR, 23)
Thus
statements about the empirical world belong to a different field than statements
about the profound repetition at its heart. Moreover, there is a third field
“between” the two. A third kind of ontological claim can be made about that
which lies “between the levels or
degrees of a repetition which is total and totalizing” (DR, 287). This is the field of difference.
We might also call it the virtual field, since it has to do with ideal
structures that are “drawn from”(DR, 287) the inner repetition and that
get “incarnated” (DR, 267) in the
world of objects. Deleuze denotes these ideal structures with a variety of
terms: Ideas, events, intensities, and singularities. Explaining just how these
terms are related would take us too far afield. What they all share is that they
bridge the two repetitions. Difference is “between two repetitions: between the
superficial repetition of the identical and instantaneous external elements that
it contracts, and the profound repetition of the internal totalities of an
always variable past” (DR, 287).
We find
a remarkably similar scheme in The Logic
of Sense. Deleuze again speaks of a field of virtual structures, a field of
difference “behind” the empirical world. But unlike Difference and Repetition, The
Logic of Sense concentrates on one particular kind of virtual structure –
namely, events. Events
are not bodies but,
properly speaking, “incorporeal” entities. They are not physical qualities and properties,but
rather logical or dialectical attributes. . . . We cannot say that they exist,
but rather that they subsist or inhere (having this minimum of being which is
appropriate to that which is not a thing, a nonexisting entity). (LS, 4–5)
Events
belong to the virtual field, since they are “ideal by nature” (LS, 53) and are not to be confused with
their “spatio-temporal realizations in states of affairs” (LS, 149). Statements about events are fundamentally different from
statements about “physical qualities and properties” (LS, 4). Events are “not
what occurs” but are “rather inside what occurs” (LS, 149). But at the same time, Deleuze is careful to distinguish
events from what he calls the Event. Events (with a lower-case “e”)
“communicate in one and the same Event” (LS,
53). They are the “bits and pieces” of the Event, which Deleuze calls “the
paradoxical instance… in which all events communicate and are distributed” (LS, 56). Deleuze seems to equate the
Event with Being – he claims it is that in virtue of which entities are. The
Event occurs “Eventum tantum for all
events, the ultimate form for all of the forms which remain disjointed in it,
but which bring about the resonance and the ramification of their disjunction.
The univocity of Being merges with the positive use of the disjunctive
synthesis which is the highest affirmation. It is the eternal return itself, or…
one Being for all forms and all times” (LS,
179–180). So again we have a tripartite division of ontological fields: the
Event; events, or ideal states of difference which “communicate” in the Event;
and the world of material objects, which is the “spatio-temporal realization” (LS, 149) of these ideal events. This
scheme is so similar to the one found in Difference
and Repetition that it must be the same one, with minor changes in
terminology. The Event corresponds to the “good” or “secret” repetition; the
material world corresponds to the “bad” repetition, or the repetition of the
same; and the field of events corresponds to the difference lying between the two
repetitions.Each field is distinct from the other two. So statements about one
have a different ontological status than statements about another.
Thus
Deleuze’s ontology is based on a tripartite distinction among Being, the virtual,
and the actual. Let me say a little more about each. First, Being is synonymous
with the Event or the good repetition. Claims about Being are not to be
confounded with claims about entities, whether actual (material objects) or
virtual (such as Ideas). As I suggested above,Deleuze understands Being in the
pronominal mode. He views it as something like expressive agency, something
like movement or force. More specifically, he views it as the activity of
differentiation [8] – a destabilizing or decentring force which shatters fixed
identities. One might think of this by analogy with Heraclitus’s primordial
fire. In both cases, Being is seen as an incendiary force, a force which makes
different and makes difference. Paradoxically, it is because Deleuze
understands Being as a differentiating agency that he sees Being as univocal. All entities arise through
differentiation; to be an entity at all is to have an “identity swallowed up in
difference” (DR, 56). All entities
“share” difference. In this way, “difference immediately reunites and
articulates what it distinguishes” (DR,
170).
But to
to say that Being “is” univocal is not to say that it is predicated only of the
actual – that is, of states of affairs in space and time. Like Duns
Scotus,Deleuze maintains that virtual structures areas well, though not in the
same way actual entities are. Being, Deleuze argues, should be understood as “extra-Being, that is, the minimum of
Being common to the real, the possible, and the impossible” (LS, 180). Hence his famous insistence
that virtual structures such as Ideas are “real without being actual” [9]. For
Deleuze, the former predicate has a wider extension than the latter. Nor should
Being be seen as the ground of entities, at least not in any usual sense of
“ground.” Since Being is understood as that which decentres or destabilizes –
in short, as that which “makes” difference – we might rather think of it as “a
repetition of ungrounding”(DR, 200). Deleuze wants to say, paradoxically,
that the only “ground” entities have in common is the lack of a common ground.
That in virtue of which all things are, is the activity of differentiation.
Deleuze’s
second field is the virtual. Again, this field concerns the differential states
or structures which lie “between” the two repetitions, between the secret
repetition associated with Being and the repetition of the same associated with
the empirical world. The field of difference should be distinguished from both.
It is a “transcendental field which does not resemble the corresponding
empirical fields, and which nevertheless is not confused with an
undifferentiated depth” (LS, 102).
The entities associated with the virtual are all ideal structures (though
“ideal without being abstract” (WP,
156)): Ideas, intensities, singularities, and events. Like Duns Scotus’s
virtual properties, these structures cannot be isolated in material actuality,
though they reveal something true of the actual. A battle, to borrow one of
Deleuze’s examples, is something real, and to say that a battle is taking place
is to give a correct description of something going on in the actual world. At
the same time, a battle is not an isolable, spatio-temporal state of affairs.
It is virtual
because it is
actualized in diverse manners at once, and because each participant may grasp
it at a different level of actualization within its variable present. . . . But
it is above all because the battle hovers over its own field, being neutral in
relation to all its temporal actualizations, neutral and impassive in relation
to the victor and the vanquished, the coward and the brave. (LS, 100)
An
event, like any virtual structure, is “Something”(LS, 157) without being a thing. It is
real but not localizable. Thus it is not something possible, even though
virtual structures get actualized in much the same way as possibilities get
realized. Unlike the possible, the virtual does not need to be realized, because “it possesses a full reality by
itself” (DR, 211). Moreover, to
conflate the virtual with the possible is to see the virtual as a mere image of
the real, an image which gets existence added to it. If, like Deleuze, we view
Being as that which makes different and makes difference, there is no room for
such a view.
Deleuze’s
final field is the actual, which is synonymous with ‘material world.’ In both Difference and Repetition and The Logic of Sense, Deleuze sees the
material world as a manifestation of principles which, though immanent to it,
are not actually part of it. It is the actualization of virtual structures.
Deleuze therefore speaks of the actual as “an external envelope or a detachable
shell” which is “animated by the other repetition” (DR, 289) – that is, by the Event. He also calls it the
spatio-temporal realization of virtual structures. Of course, this does not
mean that the empirical world is just in space and time, as if these were
passive, indifferent media. On the contrary, Deleuze wants to say that space
and time are some how constituted through the activity of differentiation. Thus
he speaks of “the production of existence occurring in a characteristic space
and time” (DR, 211).
We are
now in a better position to understand the different types of ontological
claims Deleuze makes, and to see what sets them apart. But while Deleuze’s tripartite
scheme clarifies some issues, it obfuscates others. For one thing, it is not
immediately clear why he invokes three fields. Why not two, or four? Moreover,
Deleuze is unclear on how the fields are related. He often suggests that they
are linked causally. In Difference and
Repetition, for instance, he claims that the inner repetition “should be
regarded as the cause, of which the bare material and horizontal repetition
(from which a difference is merely drawn off) is only an effect” (DR, 289). The Logic of Sense,however, invokes the Stoic notion of surface
effects to suggest that any causal chain linking the three fields goes in the
opposite direction, with the material somehow causing both the virtual and the
Event. He argues that in any reversal of Platonism – and he considers his own
thought such a reversal – “impassive extra-Being” becomes seen as “sterile,
inefficacious, and on the surface of things: the
ideational or the incorporeal can no longer be anything other than an ‘effect’”(LS, 7). What is Deleuze up to here? Just
what relation holds among the three ontological fields? To answer this question,
I now take a necessary detour through Spinoza’s account of expression. Doing so
will shed some light on how Being, the virtual, and the actual are related.
2. Spinoza as expressionist
It is impossible
to understand Spinoza’s views on expression without grasping the role of
immanence in his thought. Spinoza’s entire philosophy could be seen as an ontology
of pure immanence.This means two things. First, Spinoza sees Being as univocal.
Being “is” one, and everything that is, in so far as it is, has a common,
unitary ground. Second, that in virtue of which all entities are is somehow in
them – it is not, say, a transcendent creator-God, or a Neoplatonic One from
which they emanate. Entities manifest a ground with which they are in some
sense identical. This ground is substance – for Spinoza,to be an entity at all
is to exist “in” or “through” the one substance, to be a modification of that
substance’s essence.Nothing can be or be conceived outside of substance. All
things are “in” it. Unitary Being is immanent in its diverse manifestations.
But
what entitles Spinoza to claim that all entities are manifestations of an
immanent, unitary ground? Basically, it is his insistence that the one
substance can be understood in two different ways. Substance can be seen from
the standpointof its essence,or what it is in itself; or from the standpoint of
its existence, or what it is in actuality. Essence and existence, though
formally distinct, are not really
distinct. They are not different things.
They are, as it were, dynamically identical [10].The essence of substance is
absolutely infinite power, and more specifically, the absolutely unlimited power
to exist and generate effects. Spinoza equates essence and power at several
points in the Ethics. He states, for
instance, that “God’s power is identical with his essence” [11]. Similarly, he claims
that “the potentiality of existenceis a power,” and that the greater a thing’s
essence, “so also will it increase its strength for existence” (E, 53). So substance’s essence is the
absolutely infinite power to exist and generate effects. But things are not the
same with respect to the existence of substance. Substance actually exists as
mode, as the “things” which follow from its essence and which express that
essence determinately. Substance’s essence gives rise to an infinity of modes in
an infinity of ways. Thus substance actually exists not as the power to generate
effects, but as those effects. And each expresses, to the extent that it can,
substance’s essence.
To say this
differently, substance is both active and passive, both expressive agency and
the expressed enactments of that agency. In essence, substance is natura naturans, or ‘nature naturing.’
It is unlimited productive force, considered in abstraction from any
manifestation of that force. But seen from another perspective, substance is
just as much the enactments of this agency. It is natura naturata, or ‘nature natured’ – power rendered exhaustively
determinate in act. Thus natura naturans
expresses itself in natura naturata.
At the same time, “the existence of God and his essence are one and the same ”(E, 63), and the possibility of viewing
substance from two perspectives does not make substance divisible or multiple. Natura naturans and natura naturata are not different things. Rather, the former is
expressed immanently in the latter. Hence the advantage of thinking Being as
power. Power is precisely a One that is a Many. It is a unitary, “pent-up”
phenomenon whose nature is to pass over into a flux of appearances with which it
is identical.Thus we can distinguish power and its manifestations in a
philosophical analysis, but they are actually the same thing considered in different
ways [12 ].So in identifying substance’s essence with power, Spinoza is able to
keep essence and existence formally distinct without tempting his readers to
see them as different things. He is able to say both that natura naturans grounds and expresses itself in natura naturata, and that this ground is
identical with its manifestations. Expression – the movement from power to act –
is the concept Spinoza uses to develop an ontology of immanence.
Deleuze
bases his reading of Spinoza on the notion of expression. Indeed, he claims
that Spinoza’s greatest achievement is his expressionistic understandingof
Being. “With Spinoza,” Deleuze claims, “univocal being ceases to be neutralized
and becomes expressive” (DR, 40). Two
things about expression particularly fascinate Deleuze. One is that in every
case, “expression presents us with a triad” (EP, 27). Whenever we speak of a power expressing itself in act, we
must distinguish three terms: that which “expresses itself,” that “which
expresses,” and that “which is expressed” (EP,
27). It is no accident that expression forces us to distinguish three terms. In
Deleuze’s view, expression always involves three terms, and “remains
unintelligible while we see only two of the terms whose relations it presents”
(EP, 27). Accordingly, Deleuze’s
reading of the Ethics – the
expressionistic ontology par excellence
– is full of references to triads and triadic structures [13]. He claims, for
instance, that the essence of substance cannot be understood apart from a triad
of properties, namely “perfect,” “infinite,” and “absolute” (EP, 337). Similarly, he claims that
Spinoza’s understanding of conatus is
based on an “individual modal triad: essence, capacity to be affected, [and]
the affections that exercise this capacity” (EP, 339). But the most fundamental triad around which Spinoza’s
thought turns is “the remarkable division into substance, attribute and modes”
(DR, 40). To view substance as
expressive is to distinguish three terms: substance, or “that which is in itself,
and is conceived through itself;” attribute, or that which “constitutes” or
“expresses” the essence of substance in a particular way; and mode, or “that
which exists in, and is conceived through,” attributes (E, 45). Deleuze, in short, understands Spinoza’s substance in terms
of three distinct fields, and argues that this understanding is dictated by the
logic of expression.
The
second aspect of expression that fascinates Deleuze is that it is a double
movement, a duplicating movement. We never encounter expression simpliciter; rather, “expression,
through its own movement, generates a second level of expression” (EP, 105). In other words, “expression
has within it the sufficient reason of a re-expression” (EP, 105). But how does expression at the first level differ from its
re-expression at the second? Simply put, the first is a process of
determination. When power expresses itself in act, it first casts itself into
some determinate form. Hence Deleuze’s description of this movement as “formal”
or “qualitative” (EP, 165). Deleuze
has in mind the relation of substance to its attributes here. Each attribute
“expresses eternal and infinite essentiality” (E, 45), but in one determinate way. Thus Thought and Extension both
express the essence of substance, but determine that essence into different
forms. Once this first expressionhas taken place – once substance is considered
under one attribute rather than another – substance re-expresses itself at a
second level [14]. More specifically, “the attributes are in their turn
expressed: they express themselves in modes which designate them, the modes
expressing a modification” (EP, 105).
Each mode expresses the power of substance,after its own fashion and to the
extent that it can. So “this second level defines production itself: God is said
to produce things, as his attributes find expression” (EP,108). And since production is always of particular modes,
Deleuze says that “the production of modes [takes] place through
differentiation” (EP, 182–183). Thus
expression comprises two movements: one from substance to attribute, the other
from attribute to mode. The first is qualitative expression, through which
substance renders itself determinate in certain (infinite) forms. The second is
quantitative expression, through which these forms express themselves in turn
through the production of particular modes. Expression comprises both
determination and differentiation.
So much
for Deleuze’s reading of Spinoza. Let me now explain what light it sheds on his
own ontology.
3. Deleuze as Spinozist
Some
similarities between Spinoza’s ontology of immanence and Deleuze’s ontology of
difference have, no doubt, already suggested themselves. But the two most important
similarities parallel the two main themes of Expressionism in Philosophy. First, Deleuze’s ontology, like
Spinoza’s, invokes a triad. Just as Spinoza’s ontology revolves around the
triad of substance, attribute, and mode, so does Deleuze’s ontology revolve
around the triad of Being, the virtual, and the actual. And this is no
coincidence. Deleuze’s ontology must invoke three distinct ontological fields,
becausehe, like Spinoza, understands Being in the pronominal. He views it in
terms of power or expressive agency. Of course, Deleuze and Spinoza do not understand
this agency in precisely the sameway.For Spinoza, it is the absolutely infinite
power to exist and generate effects. For Deleuze, it is something like the activity
of differentiation, a power of divergence or decentring to which “the entire
alternative between finite and infinite applies very badly” (DR, 264). Nevertheless, both understand Being as a power which
expresses itself in act. Consequently, they distinguish this power both from
the qualitatively different forms into which it determines itself, and from the
quantitatively different entities which actualize those forms.For Spinoza,the determinate
forms are attributes and the actualizations are modes; for Deleuze, the forms
are ideal structures such as Ideas and events,while the actualizations are
empirical entities. So for both Spinoza and Deleuze, the attempt to view Being
as expressive requires us to distinguish three ontological fields. This tripartite
scheme is dictated by the logic of expression.
Second,
Deleuze, like Spinoza, makes use of the notion of double expression. For
Deleuze as for Spinoza, “expression has within it the sufficient reason of a
re-expression” (EP, 105). When we say
that Being expresses itself, we must distinguish two stages. First, Being
determines itself into certain forms; next, those forms get actualized through
the production of particular things. In Difference
and Repetition, Deleuze distinguishes expression from re-expression by distinguishing
differentiation from differenciation. Differentiation is a “formal” or “qualitative”
(EP,165) process. It is “the determination
of the virtual content of an Idea” (DR,
207), or, more generally, the process through which Being renders itself
determinate in ideal structures. Some of these structures get incarnated in the
material world through the process of differenciation, which Deleuze calls “the
actualization of [a] virtuality into species and distinguished parts” (DR, 207). Virtual structures are forced
to differenciate themselves.Indeed, as Deleuze writes in Bergsonism, “the characteristic of virtuality is to exist in such a
way that it is actualized by being differentiated andis forced to differentiate
itself, to create its lines of differentiation in order to be actualized” [15].
For Deleuze, the actual does not resemble the virtual, and a material entity is
not a copy of the Idea it incarnates. On the contrary, to actualize an Idea is
precisely to differ and diverge from this structure – “the nature of the
virtual is such that, for it, to be actualizedis to be differenciated” (DR, 211). While organisms incarnate
biological Ideas, and social entities incarnate social Ideas, these material
systems do not resemble that of which they are the actualizations. To be an
actualization in the first place is precisely to differ from such virtual
structures. So like Spinoza, Deleuze sees expression as a double movement, the
dual process of determination and actualization. The movement from Being to the
virtual parallels that from substance to attribute; the movement from virtual
to actual parallels that from attribute to mode. Deleuze’s conception of
expression is, at bottom, a slightly modified version of Spinoza’s.
The
upshot of all this is that in Difference
and Repetition and The Logic of Sense,
Deleuze is working with a Spinozistic model of expression. Those unfamiliar
with Deleuze’s work on Spinoza are bound to miss important parts of his own
expressive ontology. They will fail to see why Deleuze carefully distinguishes
difference from the two repetitions that surround it, events from the Event.
They will fail to see exactly why differentiation is not differenciation, why
determination is not actualization. But to say that Deleuze uses a Spinozistic
model of expression is not to deny that there are crucial differences between
the two. There are many. For one thing, Deleuze makes clear that actualization,
as he understands it, is not realization. It is not the process through which
something merely possible has existence “added” to it and becomes real. It is
rather the process through which the virtual – already fully real, in so far as
it is virtual – differenciates itself. Spinoza, on the other hand, seems to view
natura naturans as a potential which does get realized in natura naturata. After all, substance’s
power is precisely the power to exist. No doubt Deleuze would see it as the
power to add existence to essences that are merely possible. The distinction between
virtuality and possibility is, therefore, one rift between Spinoza and Deleuze.
Another is the way in which they understand the notion of ground. For Spinoza, natura naturans grounds natura naturata by expressing itself in
it. To the extent that all modes are modifications of the one substance, they
are all expressions of the same “thing.” Deleuze wants to distance himself from
this understanding of “ground.” If the entities in Deleuze’s universe have
anything in common, it is, paradoxically, the activity of “ungrounding” (DR, 292) out of which they originate.
All things “share” difference. What they have in common is the lack of anything
in common. In this respect as well, Deleuze parts company with Spinoza, while
at the same time describing himself as a Spinozist.
The
greatest difference between the two, however, has to do with a brief remark
Deleuze makes in Difference and
Repetition. Let me close with it.
With Spinoza,
univocal being ceases to be neutralized and becomes expressive; it becomes a
truly expressive and affirmative proposition. Nevertheless, there still remains
a difference between substance and the modes: Spinoza’s substance appears
independent of the modes, while the modes are dependent on substance, as though
on something other than themselves. (DR,
40)
Deleuze
thinks that although Spinoza is the
philosopher of immanence, his treatment of substance still contains a residue
of transcendence or emanation. Spinoza, in Deleuze’s view, privileges substance
over mode. How so? One possible answer– and perverse as it may seem– is that
Spinoza philosophizes before Heidegger, Deleuze after. Despite Deleuze’s
apparent indifference to Heidegger, he does seem to accept the validity of the
ontological difference. Deleuze carefully distinguishes Being from entities.
But Spinoza does not, and cannot, because he identifies Being with substance. Substance
is. Spinoza thinks of it as a being, albeit a being fundamentally different
from the “beings” we call modes. For Spinoza, there is a sense in which substance
and modes are both “things,” in so far as both are. But the former is more real, so it is a bigger and better
thing. This violates what Deleuze sees as the first rule of an ontology of
immanence – namely, that Being be “equally present in all beings,” and that
entities not be “defined by their rank in a hierarchy” (EP, 173). Spinoza, despite his preoccupation with immanence, seems
at the end of the day to think that Being is not equally present in all entities. He seems to rank entities
hierarchically, and to rank substance more highly than mode.
Deleuze
will have no truck with this view. He is adamant that substance “be said of the modes and only of the modes” (DR, 40). As I suggested above, he wants “to make substance turn
around [its] modes” (DR, 304). He
does not want the realm of particular empirical things to be subordinate to
anything. This, I take it, is what he is up to when he bridges Being and the
actual with the virtual (instead of with, say, attributes). As I have
repeatedly urged, virtual things are,
but are not actual. They are “surface effects” (LS, 4) on the actual. The only actual things there are belong to
the third field, the material field. The first and second fields do not “contain”
any actual things – since Being is not, and virtual structures are not actual –
so there can be no question of anything having “more” Being than material
entities. There can be no hierarchy of entities. Being “is” equally present in
all entities, and so “is” truly univocal.
I have
tried to show that Deleuze is a Spinozist, and that certain themes in his work
make sense only in a Spinozist context. I have also suggested that part of what
draws him to Spinoza is the ideal of pure immanence – that is, Spinoza’s search
for an ontology in which Being is said equally of all things. But Spinoza, in
Deleuze’s view, cannot realize this goal as long as he privileges substance
over mode. To the extent that Deleuze tries to make substance turn on its
modes, he might be seen as an even greater thinker of immanence than Spinoza.
Perhaps, then, Deleuze is not just a Spinozist. Perhaps he is a more
thorough-going Spinozist than Spinoza.
Piercey,
Robert. “The Spinoza-intoxicated Man: Deleuze on Expression”, Man and World [Continental Philosophy Review], vol. 29, no. 3, Kluwer, Dordrecht,
1996, pp. 269–281.
Notes
1.
Gilles Deleuze, Expressionism in
Philosophy: Spinoza, trans. Martin Joughin (New York: Zone Books, 1992),
11. Hereafter cited parenthetically as EP.
2.
Gilles Deleuze, Difference and Repetition,
trans. Paul Patton (London: Athlone, 1994), 304. Hereafter cited
parenthetically as DR.
3.
Constantin Boundas, “Deleuze: Serialization and Subject-Formation.” Gilles Deleuze and the Theater of Philosophy,
ed. Constantin Boundas and Dorothea Olkowski (New York: Routledge, 1994), 101.
4.
Gilles Deleuze, The Logic of Sense,
trans. Mark Lester and Charles Stivale, ed. Constantin Boundas (New York:
Columbia University Press, 1990), 179. Hereafter cited parenthetically as LS.
5. For
a very different view, see Nick Land, “Making it with Death: Remarks on
Thanatos and Desiring-Production.” The
Journal of the British Society for Phenomenology 24/1 (Jan. 1993) 66–76.
6. My
emphasis.
7. For
a detailed and recent discussion of this point, see Deleuze’s “L’immanence: une
vie . . .” in Philosophie 47 (Sept.
1995) 3–7.
8. For
now, I do not distinguish differentiation from differenciation.
9.
Gilles Deleuze and Félix Guattari, What
is Philosophy?, trans. Graham Burcell and Hugh Tomlinson (London: Verso,
1994), 156. Hereafter cited parenthetically as WP.
10. I
am indebted to D.V. Maxwell on this point. Indeed, my entire reading of Spinoza
owes a great deal to Professor Maxwell.
11.
Spinoza, The Ethics, in Works of Spinoza, Volume 1, trans. and
ed. R.H.M. Elwes (New York: Dover, 1955), 74. Hereafter cited parenthetically
as E.
12. As
will be obvious, my treatment of power owes a great deal to Hegel’s discussion
of force and the understanding. See the Phenomenology
of Spirit, trans. A.V. Miller (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1977),
79–103.
13. For
an extensive list, see EP 337–342.
14. Of course, the first expression need not be thought of as temporally prior to the second.
15.
Gilles Deleuze, Bergsonism, trans.
Hugh Tomlinson and Barbara Habberjam (New York: Zone Books, 1991), 97.
14. Of course, the first expression need not be thought of as temporally prior to the second.
No hay comentarios.:
Publicar un comentario