Leszek Kolakowski
Monist doctrines always have trouble with the idea of
negative freedom. It is only with great effort, and at enormous cost, that they
succeed in salvaging it within their constructions; indeed it is doubtful
whether this has ever been achieved without sacrificing coherence. Perfect
solipsism aside (never seriously proposed and existing only in the realm of the
imaginable), the monist project – to interpret all the qualities of existence as
relative to one primordial being – inevitably ends up abolishing the entire
realm of the subjective (understood as an irreducible realm). In this
relativized monist world, subjectivity is always a particular state, arrangement,
manifestation or phenomenon of something else – something that is not
subjective – and can thus be defined entirely in terms of the object.
Belief in freedom as a negative quality of the subject is
the belief that some if not all actions of the self-knowing subject have an
unconditioned beginning: a perfect, ultimate source and spontaneous origin. It
presupposes that when we ask about the reasons for our freely-made decisions, we
will always reach an impassable barrier, a point where our question can go no
further: the ultimate reason of our wanting something is, in the end, simply
our wanting it – just that and no more. I can always ask why I want one thing
rather than another, and sometimes I will be able to find an answer, but each
new answer will be another “because I want . . .” After a number of such
answers, going further and further back, the chain of explanations comes to an
end, and I am left only with “I want this just because this is what I want.”
A subject to which we attribute this ability to evade
determination, to refuse the question concerning the reasons for its own
choices, is one whose every action must be considered as an unconditioned
beginning: a new and unpredictable act of self-creation; a crack, or rather a
kind of self-formed whirlpool, in the great mass of existence. Thus there are
as many absolutes as there are self-conscious subjects capable of choice: at every
point of subjectivity in the universe, the unity of the divine absolute, or of
the absolute of nature, breaks down. When we consider this, we can appreciate the
difficulties with which the scholastics had to grapple in their search a
non-contradictory formula that would reconcile God’s definition as the absolute
and only beginning with freedom of choice – a freedom that determines ex
nihilo but is not itself predetermined. The search is ultimately pointless,
the solutions proposed fragile as porcelain, and the results paltry; but the
huge efforts expended by Christianity, in all its varieties, to avoid the
either/or – the disjunctive choice between divine omnipotence and human freedom
– also have their roots in the monist temptation, present in the doctrine of
creation.
Cartesianism disentangled itself from this predicament
through the epistemological decision expressed in the cogito. The cogito
allows us, in fact compels us, to salvage our own existence – existence as
it is experienced by us; it is the uniquely compelling starting-point of
thinking about existence. As a result, we can more easily endow this
epistemological primacy with ontic meaning. Indeed we cannot avoid doing so: if
we tried – if we considered that what is “given” in the most primary sense is
merely an appearance – then we could not legitimately pass from the appearance
to the reality. But the cognitive absoluteness of a self-directed act of thinking
endows that act with the right to claim absoluteness in the ontic order for
itself as well. Consequently, freedom is not hopelessly entangled in the
shackles of divine Grace as soon as we begin to think about it; its foundations
can be built long before we are even aware of such a thing as divine Grace. We
do not need to rescue it with excuses and evasions. Cartesian freedom, being
negative, knows no restrictions; it is, from the start, simply our inalienable
ability to add our own fiat to that of God. This is something we do with
each act of subjective consciousness, and through each such act we become equal
with our creator. It is a freedom that lies in the power of our self-defined
creativity to choose.
But the Cartesian construction suffers from a fundamental
lack of continuity, for which there is no cure. How are we to go about
reconstructing the world if the only absolute, unconditioned starting-point is the
self-intentional act of consciousness – an act in which experience acquires
just enough distance towards itself to glimpse itself for a fleeting moment in
the act of reflection which splits it in two? Descartes’ famous appeal to God
as the guarantor of truth, the savior of our belief in the reality of heaven
and earth, was almost immediately revealed by his critics to be riddled with
holes so gaping that the majority of Cartesians preferred to renounce it; and
the very first critics found that the Cartesian construction, for all its
monumental sweep, was organically incapable of reconstructing physical
existence from its initial principles. Freedom – the negativity which defines
the particularity of human existence – remained a reward promised to those
willing to suspend judgment about the reality of the world.
Thus Cartesianism split philosophies into two distinct
groups: those that start from the experience of the subject and try to return
to the objective world from there – a feat they can accomplish only through
invalid proofs; and those that start from existence itself, establishing it without
anyone’s cognitive assistance – which bars the road to subjectivity, so that
they are forced to treat human existence as part of objective reality, endowing
it with the same status as objects, unless they endow it with a different
status by arbitrary decree.
Spinoza’s metaphysics suffers from exactly the opposite
problem. Whereas Descartes wanted to build up the external world from the raw data
of our mental experience, the cogito, Spinoza’s starting-point (at least
in the Ethics) was the unique, absolute, primary being; divine
substance, definitively established by ontological proof, was the material of thought.
This metaphysical picture leaves no room for self-consciousness, and Spinoza’s
doctrine struggles in vain to find a way of accommodating it. For what does it
mean to say that to be human is to have not only a body but also a soul, a soul
not existentially identical with that body, if we, like all other things in the
world, are modifications of infinite substance, and like them partake of that ideal
or “mental” quality in which each individual existence shares? We are “soul”
only to the extent that everything is. One thing only makes us specifically
human: the fact that, in addition to the idea, we also have the idea of that
idea – self-consciousness, which is not given to other things. But why is it
not? The sole metaphysical justification for endowing us with it is the fact
that the idea of everything, and therefore also the idea of the idea, is in
God. But if so, one is tempted to ask why the idea of other things should not
be similarly duplicated: why should perfect being – the participation of all things
in the logical order of being – be deprived of this double endowment by virtue
of which it becomes self-knowing, so that it not only knows, but also knows
that it knows?
Spinoza refused to recognize the absurd consequences of
his metaphysics. The restriction whereby he distinguished human existence was utterly
arbitrary, with no foundation whatsoever in his metaphysical doctrine. His
critics had good reason to accuse him of haziness on this point, and good
reason to remark on his fundamental inability to take any kind of theoretical
step that might confer legitimacy on the subjective realm. They had good
reason, too, for saying that human existence cannot be reconstructed in a way
that would be consistent with the basic principles of his metaphysics; it can
be distinguished only by purely objective, empirical qualities.
Spinoza’s version of the freedom and immanent necessity
of the Absolute is not, in fact, very different from the kind of freedom that Platonist
scholastics attributed to the Creator. For Spinoza, the nature of divine
existence is such that the Absolute being cannot be said to be “free” in the
sense in which human action is commonly said to be free, i.e., non-determined,
because the Absolute does not exist in time. As a perfect being, the Absolute
is by definition extra-temporal: it cannot be bound by temporal succession or
subject to temporal change. A being for which there is a distinction between
past and future could not have the Absolute’s direct cognitive link to the
world; it would need mediation, in the form of memory and foresight. But if its
relation to events were indirect, mediated through recollection of the past or
projection into the future, its knowledge of the world would not be that direct
cognitive participation which defines the Absolute’s relation to all that
exists and takes place; it would entail a distinction between the possible and
the actual. And since it is inconceivable that for God there should be a
distinction between the possible and the actual, it is also inconceivable that He
should exist within the framework of temporal succession.
By the same token, it is inconceivable that God should
enjoy freedom from determination in the sense of being free at any given moment
to choose how He will act. God cannot choose, for choosing entails choosing
between possibilities, and He is by definition perfectly actualized; it is
inconceivable that He could be confronted with an event to which His relation
was not already determined. For God there can be no “already” and no “given
moment” in time, for there is no distinction between past and future, actuality
and potentiality. His relation to events can be said neither to be determined
nor to be pre-determined; the distinction between what is necessary and what is
free and undetermined makes no sense when applied to God. Thus God is “free”
only in the sense that He cannot be constrained or influenced by any external
circumstance – a freedom that follows logically from His definition as the absolute
Creator. This is all Spinoza means when he calls God free and His actions
necessary and inevitable: He is free because He is not constrained by anything
outside Himself, and His actions are inevitable because, being perfectly
actualized, He is bound by His own necessity. Always fully actualized in His
immobile and immutable self-identity, God is temporal only for us; the
framework of individual events, causally linked and succeeding each other in
time, exists only in our perception. But in fact past and future are both
actualized, for they are actualized in God-Nature. He is the only reality, the
only independent being; apart from Him there is nothing, and nothing else
merits the name of being in the true sense.
In this absolute unity of being there is no crack that
could shatter God’s primordial self-identity, no imaginable opening through
which something as yet undetermined could in the course of time become determined.
Nor can we imagine this God engaged in any purposive activity, for God can have
no purpose that is not yet fulfilled: purposive action is evidence of
imperfection; it implies something not achieved, some need unsatisfied. But the
Absolute being is completely fulfilled; it would be blasphemy to say that God
acts towards a goal. Everything that will ever happen in the world has already
happened; it is already a fact. There can be no hope of any spontaneous, freely
self-determined irruption into the inevitable succession of events, no possible
break of their continuity. Such a break would be a break in the chain of
logical consequence: it would mean that something that follows logically from a
given proposition or state of affairs could be made not to follow from it by an
arbitrary decision, a whim. For the course of physical events proceeds with the
same inevitability as that with which conclusions follow from premises in
Euclid’s Elements. Thus the very nature of the Absolute is such that
there can be neither contingency nor purposiveness in the world – unless we
decide to consider as contingent everything whose causes are unknown to us. But
that contingency would be related to our own ignorance, not to any property of
being itself.
Given these principles, the absurdity of attributing what
we commonly call free will to the human individual is so glaring that it would scarcely
be worth pointing out but for the fact that we do so attribute it, and for the
singular role played in our lives by the persistent illusion of free will,
maintained by theologians in the face of all common sense. Spinoza believes the
illusion to be so childishly easy to shatter that the task seems almost beneath
his dignity; the ample space he devotes to the problem is owing only to its
social importance, not to its philosophical complexity. For since everything is
in God and nothing apart from God can be conceived, and since, further, God
exists necessarily, it follows that every manifestation of His indifferent
(i.e., non-purposive) creative power is also necessary; and in particular that
“reason and will are [proper] to God’s nature [in the same way] as movement and
rest.” Thus human behavior is just like the behavior of all other things: no
less dependent, no freer, no more self-determined, no more purposive. Our power
of choice is illusory. Whatever happens happens because it must; whatever does
not happen does not happen because it cannot. In reality there is no middle
ground between impossibility and necessity: what we think of as the realm of
the contingent exists only in our imagination, and reflects our defective
understanding of the world.
Divested of the peculiarly Spinozean vocabulary in which
it is couched, this metaphysics may be summed up as follows. The world is indifferent
to the fact that we are part of it. It has no intentions towards us, either
hostile or friendly. In its perfection it has actualized everything than can
exist. It has no aim, and does not intend to change anything in view of human
suffering; indeed, is inconceivable that it would or could. There is no
providence in the world; nothing protects us or watches over our lives. There
is neither punishment nor reward, neither good nor evil, neither justice nor
injustice. Good and evil, justice and injustice, exist in the world only
through and for us, called into existence by our needs. Nature is not
interested in our constructs.
But here is the paradox: the thing that makes us uniquely
human, that inalienable feature of our existence which is its ability to
experience itself, is metaphysically quite groundless; and yet it is the source
not only of our specificity as human beings but also of our erroneous ideas
about that specificity. In other words, the very thing that makes us human also
gives rise to our misconceptions about what it is to be human; and that thing
has no logical connection whatsoever with the rest of Spinoza’s metaphysical
doctrine. The world according to Spinoza knows everything, but does not know
that it knows. We know pitifully little, but know that we know, and what we
don’t know, we know that we don’t know. Our physical behavior is subject to the
same necessity as the movement of waves on the surface of the sea or the
movement of a rock falling from a cliff-face. If a rock had our capacity of self-knowledge
and could understand its movements, it would imagine, just as we do, that it controls
them; it would think it was falling downwards rather than flying upwards as a
result of its own free choice. But its movements are determined in exactly the
same way as our actions; we have no more freedom than the rock. Our observation
of ourselves is just that and no more – powerless observation; and it is this
very capacity of self-observation that deludes us into thinking, with pathetic
arrogance, that it is we who are the creative force behind our physical
movements, which in fact are all purely mechanical. There is no efficient
causal connection between our thought and our movement: we observe our own
bodies as through a pane of glass, imagining that we control them, like boys
who play at pretending to control thunder by ordering a thunderclap just at the
moment when it comes.
Are we, then, not responsible even for our own bodies,
buffeted about independently of our will, at the mercy of forces exerted by the
motion of material particles? Spinoza would reply that here, again, the question
is wrongly put; it is like asking why, in that case, we should lock away
criminals, if we think they are not responsible for their actions. When we lock
away criminals, we do so in order to protect society from harm, not because the
criminal determines himself “freely” in his criminality; we act from the
instinct of self-preservation, exactly as we would in killing a poisonous snake
or removing a rock that blocks our path. We do not remove the rock or kill the
snake because we consider them to be free, and similarly with the criminal: he
is no freer than they. Nor can responsibility be identified with the absence of
determination: there is no such thing as a non-determined human decision, nor
any action that is not the result of a necessary causality. Responsibility in
this sense does not exist in the world; it is the product of our deluded
imagination.
A bad doctrine, said Spinoza’s critics; a dismal,
hopeless philosophy.
I don’t know whether it is good or bad, Spinoza replied;
all I know is that it is true.
But how wretched, they said, how tragic, to live in such
a world!
Knowledge of the truth can never be tragic and wretched,
he replied; and a life based on illusion cannot be happy. And anyway, why
tragic and wretched? To understand the true nature of the universe, to grasp
its infinite perfection, its total self-sufficiency, is to love it for what it
really is. This love is not the kind of love we would feel for another person;
it comes from reason, and is arrived at by mental effort. It cannot be returned,
nor do we expect its return, for it knows, being rooted in our understanding,
that the Absolute is not subject to emotions. But it is a happy love, for it
can never disappoint us, and through it we can free ourselves from the vain
hope that the world might be different from what it is. Our only freedom is the
freedom of the Stoics – the understanding of necessity; and it is freedom
insofar as all independence of spirit in a situation which we are powerless to
control can be called freedom. If we recognize this, we can attain the position
of disinterested observers, untouched by human passions, indifferent to
quarrels, despair, suffering or injury, able to contemplate them with the same
dispassionate equanimity that characterizes the chains of our logical reasoning
about abstract geometry. The effort required to achieve this state will have
been well worth it: no more absurd regrets, grudges against the world, railings
against fate that it has not treated us as we think we deserve; no more
bitterness at failure and thwarted ambition; no more outrage at human
wickedness or horror at the sight of evil; no more vain and fruitless pity. All
this we shall rise above, to enjoy the happy certainty that we are part of an
infinite whole, with whose timeless, eternal existence we can to some extent
identify, since we have grasped it. We shall no longer be afraid of death,
oblivion or damnation, for in a world whose necessity we truly love we shall
see death as an inevitable part of a perfectly coherent whole.
A masochist’s philosophy, commented the historian Lewis
Samuel Feuer. Who else could find joy in the boundless indifference of the absolute
world, a source of happiness in loving it with an unreciprocated love, a cause
for rejoicing in an order of things that destroys us as inevitably as the wind
shakes the leaves off trees, eternally imposing its irresistible force on our
frail powers? A resigned mystic’s, let us say, rather than a masochist’s: the
philosophy of a mystic who has clothed his personal mysticism in Cartesian concepts
and categories. An escapist philosophy; a theory of freedom attained through
the spiritual denial of the finite order of the world.
But we know this is only one aspect of Spinoza’s world.
The philosopher who would have us bow down in admiration before an immutably determined
chain of events, would have us worship a perfectly indifferent divinity and
seek freedom in understanding and accepting a world in which everything that
can ever happen has already happened – this same philosopher was also a
militant theorist of the liberal party in the Netherlands, a defender of
toleration and political freedom, a writer of partisan articles in support of
the republican movement, the author of the Tractatus Theologico-politicus,
and a vicious critic of theologians and the Church.
Chronology may explain some of these contradictions, but
it cannot explain them all. Spinoza’s metaphysics alone already contains a general
outline of that duality which characterizes both his life and his moral philosophy.
It may be that a vision of the world in which individual things have no
autonomous existence, but are entirely swallowed up in the divine Absolute,
cannot be reconciled with that other in which everything is guided by an
instinct of self-preservation and is destroyed only by violence or by death.
But both visions find expression in Spinoza’s advice to us, which is on the one
hand to flee our own finiteness and seek freedom through an intuition about
being that will unite us with the Absolute, and on the other to look after our
own interests and preserve our bodies and souls, to which end we may, if
necessary, resort to equivocation, evasion and half-truths.
No doubt this double perspective is in part explicable by
Spinoza’s view that the supreme values of life, attainable only through
persistent intellectual effort, will in any case be accessible to only a few.
Those few who do not allow the passions and concerns of everyday life to blind
them to the true order of values (not a transcendental order, established by
nature in normative form, but one where a value is simply a quality that is in
harmony with human nature, and thus strengthens our bodies or souls) cannot disagree
about them, for what they all equally enjoy –knowledge of eternal reality and
an understanding adapted to it – and can enjoy without diminishing its
enjoyment by anyone else, they will all equally value. But one cannot restrict
one’s thinking about the world of human affairs to things which are of interest
only to that tiny elite: life in a community requires rules, and these rules
must take into account our most common natural inclinations. Human nature
cannot be denied; we may praise or condemn it, but we must recognize that it
exists. It would be absurd to delude ourselves that the world of human
interaction can be sensibly ordered on the basis of the assumption that we can
all be free in the sense in which to be free is to participate in the cosmic
indifference of perfect being.
Let us consider freedom in its humbler sense – not the
freedom that comes from an understanding of reality but freedom in the sense in
which Hobbes was able to use the word consistently with his absolute belief in
universal causality. Freedom in this sense is not a human attribute, innate or
acquired, but describes a situation where nothing prevents us from doing what
we want to do (which does not, of course, imply that our wanting it is
spontaneous and undetermined by the conditions in which we find ourselves). In
other words, it is the absence of constraint. The main question Spinoza asks
about freedom in this sense is the following: since there is no supreme law
that could a priori restrict or regulate our actions, the extent of our
freedom to act being commensurate with the extent of our powers, how best
should a human community be ordered so as to minimize constraints on the
freedom of the individual while preventing the general war which would
inevitably break out if there were no laws to restrict individual actions?
His answer – at least in its general theoretical
formulation – is simple: abolish the tyranny of the Church and end its
competition with secular government; reject the demands of the clergy, who in
the name of the infallibility of their dogmas would bind the whole world in the
shackles of their catechisms; establish religious tolerance and freedom of speech
for all; maintain free trade and freedom of conscience; combat fanaticism,
superstition and claims to a monopoly on truth. But here, too, restrictions are
needed: freedom of religion, for instance, cannot be understood as extending to
anything we decide, on a whim, to define as religious; such a law would be
worthless and absurd, for it would be a license to do anything we please by
calling it religion. Freedom of religion must therefore be defined. Hence some
form of established state religion is needed – a conclusion many people in
Spinoza’s time concurred with, tired and disenchanted after a century and a
half of religious wars. A religion subject to the authority of the state could
not transform itself into a clerical despotism. Moreover, its content would be extremely
limited, comprising only those beliefs which everyone – even Spinoza – could
accept, although each could interpret them in his own way. Even Spinoza would
be willing to agree, for example, that God exists and rewards or punishes human
deeds, although he believes neither in God in the ordinary sense nor, a
fortiori, in His legislative or executive powers. But what we believe isn’t
the important thing; to each his own interpretation of the truths of faith.
What matters is that we do our duty towards our fellow men: support them in our
joint undertakings, loyally do our share, inflict no suffering and do no harm.
In its content, then, a state religion would not go beyond our basic moral
precepts and rules of behavior, and would not threaten the body politic of
tolerant state. In such a religion the Bible plays a role not because it
contains any truths about the world, for it contains none, but because it
contains those most basic teachings about how we should live and behave towards
one another – teachings which simple folk will more easily absorb through anecdotes
than through laborious philosophical inquiry. We may assume that the masses
will, in great majority, cling to their superstitious beliefs: to their belief
in God the Father, Protector and Ruler of the world; in life after death; in
heaven and hell. This is perfectly all right as long as their faith contains no
elements of fanaticism or hatred for unbelievers, and if it can accomplish what
philosophical reflection cannot, at least not on a mass scale, namely rein in
harmful passions and subdue the natural human tendency to greed, selfishness
and lust for power.
This is what Spinoza’s advice comes down to if we see it
as a series of strictly philosophical precepts within the framework of his
moral theory. It seems, when viewed in this way, quite useless: too vague, too
general, almost banal. But when we look at it in a practical rather than a purely
philosophical light, and consider it within the context of the political conflicts
in which Spinoza was embroiled as a writer, it reveals itself as rather more
substantial, and much more interesting.
From quite early on in his life, even before his
excommunication from the Jewish community, Spinoza had moved in an atmosphere
of republican freethinking. This was owing mostly to the influence of his friend
Francis van der Ende – ex-Jesuit, political radical, mocker of men and enemy of
the Church and the monarchy. Van der Ende believed in the absolute sovereignty
of the people, and he was true to his beliefs: when he became embroiled in an
anti-monarchist conspiracy in France, he demonstrated his constancy by paying
for them with his head. It is quite possible that Spinoza’s religious views
were only a pretext for his excommunication, and that the real reason lay in
his republican sentiments and allegiances: if they had somehow come to light, they
would have been considered dangerous for the Jewish community, allied by
tradition to the House of Orange. In any event, the young Spinoza, having absorbed
this atmosphere of cosmopolitan freethinking, soon came into contact with
republican politicians and activists. The Netherlands was a republic at the
time, but a frail and shaky one, swaying under the weight of constant conflict
with the aspirations of the Calvinist clergy on the one hand and the monarchist
claims of the House of Orange on the other. Spinoza’s Tractatus
Theologico-politicus was directed both at Jewish claims to be the chosen
people, with a special place in history, and at Christian claims of
infallibility; it was an attack on churches as breeding-grounds of superstition
and obscurantism; and it was a defense of toleration, democracy and
republicanism in politics. In its essentials it resembled the doctrine
expounded by the de la Court brothers – a tandem of republican theorists – in
their political and economic writings. Thus its main thesis was not
revolutionary; on the contrary, its aim was to strengthen the party in power –
a party that was weak and disorganized, and had its support base in the
interests of the liberal, peace-loving and tolerantly inclined merchant class
in the most developed cities of the United Provinces.
Most of the rest of the population was ill disposed
towards government by an enlightened elite, and from time to time made it
abundantly clear that its sympathies (fostered and stoked by the Calvinist
clergy by every means at their disposal) lay with the princes of the House of Orange.
The Protestant ethos which Spinoza so hated was well suited to organizing and
channeling the resentments of the less privileged; moments of particular
instability were deftly exploited to rally mass support for a conservative coup
– which did indeed finally take place, in 1672, at a time of military defeat.
At the moment of crisis, the freethinking patrician elite, the tolerant
republicans, the sympathizers of Arminianism in theology all found themselves
without popular support. The leaders of the republican oligarchy, the de Witt
brothers, were lynched: torn limb from limb on the streets of the Hague by a
vicious mob whipped up to a frenzy of fanaticism.
The question of democracy had to be reconsidered. If
democracy meant lawless mob violence directed by demagogues, what arguments could
Spinoza find in its favor – he, a philosopher whose sympathies lay with liberal
and freethinking but comfortably prosperous regents? He did defend democracy,
in his 1670 Treatise; but he never defended revolution in the name of
democracy. He valued not only freedom but also stability of government, and
therefore believed that it is better to submit to a tyranny than to overthrow
it by violence. Besides, democracy as he
conceived it, the democracy he defended, had always been
more a political system of reason than a system of government by the majority;
and then, he had always mistrusted the rabble. His mistrust, indeed his
contempt, is far too evident in his writings for him to have been a credible spokesman
of revolutionary tribunals. He was more concerned to inculcate the feeling of
freedom than to propagate freedom itself: to establish a rational government
which, acting on the recommendations of the Florentine master of the political
art, could through careful steering make its subjects believe that they ruled
themselves. He never achieved the synthesis he wanted: he found no way of
satisfactorily reconciling the values of freedom with those of reason and
common sense, just as he failed to reconcile the need for tolerance with the
need for stability of government.
When all the things he had condemned and opposed – the
regular army as an independent political force, the theocratic aspirations of
the clergy, the fanaticism of the mob – came into their own and became fact, Spinoza
decided it was time to revise his theory of freedom. This he
attempted to do in his unfinished Tractatus Politicus.
Here the emphasis – the way in which he formulates the issues – has shifted
somewhat by comparison with his famous earlier treatise, written in support of
the republican government then in power. True to his conviction that active political
disobedience does more harm than good, he now concentrates less on the general
question of the ideal form of government than on the problem of ensuring the
stability of various particular forms of government, monarchies included, while
preserving as much political freedom as is conceivable in the given
circumstances. But even the best laid plans will fail if we do not keep in mind
that people’s blind, thoughtless passions will always prevail over considered
analysis and rational calculation; we must never assume that human behavior
will be guided by reason. We should rather seek to harness people’s untamed
passions and exploit them for the public good.
Let us sum up.
Freedom, in Spinoza’s conception of it, is not an
attribute of human nature. In particular, it is not what we commonly call free
will – the possibility of undetermined, spontaneous, self-willed action. The
will is an abstract thing, which exists only in theory. In reality there are
only individual instances of wanting, and these are inevitably conditioned by
the circumstances in which they occur.
Nor is freedom a natural human right, a capacity we
should exploit in the name of higher values. There are no rights except that of
power and force – the power which we are able to exercise to impose our desires
on a particular situation.
If freedom is possible at all, it is our freely given
assent to the eternal and immutable order of nature; our understanding and
acceptance of nature’s indifference and lack of purpose. The freedom that comes
from this understanding is freedom from dependence on our passions: freedom from
superstition, from anger, from despair and pointless regrets, from fear of
death and of the terrors of hell. In this sense it is a negative freedom. But
it is also a positive freedom: it is the joy of knowing that one is part of the
eternal essence of the supreme being, united with it through an effort of
ultimate intuition; the happiness of intellectual love for the cosmic order.
This freedom, however, requires a certain sacrifice on our part; it can be
attained only at the cost of giving up certain things. Not just external goods
(which we will be giving up in the sense that they will have ceased to have
value for us), but also our individual identity: our self-affirmation as
separate beings. And while in theory this freedom is accessible to everyone, in
practice it can be enjoyed only by a select few. It is the supreme reward of
intellectual effort, and can be enjoyed in full by those who attain it,
regardless of their circumstances, for it is infinitely resistant to the
pressure of events and entirely insensible to the blows of fate.
This, however, is not what Spinoza means by freedom in
those passages of his writings where the word crops up most often – passages where
he is concerned to define what it means for a thing to be free in any given circumstance.
There, when he says that a thing is free, he means simply that its behavior is
not determined by external conditions. This freedom, too, characterizes
situations rather than human beings; but our understanding alone is not enough
to ensure that any given situation will be characterized by it, and it is
unclear whether it is possible at all. God is free in this way, but can this
kind of freedom also characterize human existence? Spinoza says that it can,
apparently unaware of the contradiction between this view and his own
insistence on human powerlessness and dependence on external causality. It is
hard to see how the view that our capacity of self-consciousness is no more
than passive observation, and cannot be the efficient cause of our physical actions,
could be reconciled with the view that our behavior is not, or need not be,
externally determined. And indeed, between the fully internalized freedom of
the Cartesian-style mystic and the positive freedom which affirms human
individuality through the instinct of self-preservation there can be no true
reconciliation.
These are the two faces of Spinoza – the two eyes of his
thought, one directing its escapist gaze towards the all-encompassing power of
the Absolute, the other concentrating it on the world of finite things, observed
with the dispassionate rationalism of the scientist. One eye belongs to the
apostle of deductive reasoning, the follower of Euclid, the rationalist who
attempted, and failed, to construct his metaphysics on Euclidean principles;
the other belongs to the mystic. This dual vision can perhaps be explained by
the dual aspect of Spinoza’s life: his contacts with the petit-bourgeois
mysticism of sectarian freethinkers and his involvement with the republican
bourgeoisie are certainly responsible for that other, mystical strand of his
thought, at least in its principal ideas.
Spinoza’s political doctrine, where he considers the
freedom of the individual in relation to social institutions, is similarly
marked by the uncomfortable coexistence of two conflicting tendencies, each
pulling him in a different direction. The strain produced by their conflict is expressed
in an endless indecisiveness: he is torn between his natural sympathy towards
the disinherited of the earth and his hatred of the rabble – primitive,
irrational and unpredictable; between the value of toleration and the need for
stability of government; between democracy and the need for an oligarchy of men
of reason, unsusceptible to the temptations of fanaticism and dogmatism.
His deluded and quite fantastic hope that reason alone
can enable us, always and everywhere, to act in accordance with our better
instincts is at least restricted to a select few, which slightly mitigates its
absurdity: Spinoza does not attempt to base his assessment of political systems
on it. But one suspects that there is no overlap whatsoever between the
freedoms he reserves for his select few aristocrats of the spirit and those he defends
for simple folk. For the former, the act of freely identifying with the cosmic
order and freely adoring its infinite perfection is the supreme value, next to
which all other values pale into insignificance; the select few need no more.
The wise man can lack nothing, and it is hard to see what form of coercion or
physical constraint could diminish his uniquely authentic freedom. For the
latter, on the other hand, concrete political freedoms are important values,
since that highest and most perfect form of liberation which makes all other
freedoms unnecessary is in all likelihood beyond their grasp. And such freedoms
must be secured for them, since they cannot secure them for themselves.
It is clear, when we look at Spinoza’s doctrine stripped
down to its core of fundamental ideas, that there is no way of reconciling its
inconsistencies. Its duality and internal incoherence were to bear abundant fruit
in the following century. These, roughly speaking, were as follows. Its “German
reception,” which one might qualify, very generally, as pantheistic, singled out
an idea elaborated in one part of the doctrine and present as a motif
throughout in the whole: the hope of an ultimate reconciliation with the
Absolute through the mystical abandonment of individual identity. The “French
reception” stressed the republican free-thinking aspects, generalized the
slogans calling for freedom and concentrated with satisfaction on highlighting
the anti-clerical and anti-ecclesiastical sentiments. These two perspectives,
that of the political radical and that of the metaphysician engaged in an
attempt to encompass infinite being, are so different that it seems churlish to
complain of inconsistency and lack of synthesis, as if others had succeeded
where Spinoza miserably failed: it is not as if anyone else had ever managed to
unite these two ways of looking at the world – one directed at being and one at
the subject – into a coherent whole.
And Spinoza was aware of the incoherence. He was fond of
saying, or rather of repeating after Epictetus, that human happiness and misery
depend only on the nature of the things we love; but at the same time he admitted
that he himself had been unable to free himself completely of his attachment to
those worthless goods which reason dictates that we should reject as
insignificant. So he knew that his metaphysical eye and his scientific eye were
at odds. He looked at the world through both and saw differently through each.
Thus he saw freedom alternately as mystical liberation – the proud
relinquishment of all that the world of objects has to offer – and as free
choice – that situation in which reason and intellectual effort allows us to
choose freely within the world of objects. He knew that, whether he wanted it
or not, he was part of the human world, and as such embroiled willy-nilly in
worldly concerns, conflicts and responsibilities; but as Spinoza the mystic,
the Spinoza who had rejected God and belief in immortality, he wanted to deny
his finiteness and touch being itself with his reason. He even thought he had
achieved his aim, until the disturbing questions of his more penetrating
friends undermined his certainty. Whether he died feeling satisfied or defeated
we shall never know.
Leszek Kolakowski, 'The Two Eyes of Spinoza', in The
Two Eyes of Spinoza, St. Augustine’s Press, South Bend, 2004, pp. 1-15.
No hay comentarios.:
Publicar un comentario