21 noviembre, 2011

Spinoza Contemporáneo

Lo que permanece vivo en la filosofía de Baruch de Spinoza (1632-1677) es el caudal de realidades que le preocuparon y los problemas que tales realidades le plantearon, es decir, las preguntas que motivaron radicalmente su pensamiento. Si bien sus respuestas fueron necesariamente limitadas a su tiempo y a su situación, la forma misma de tales respuestas comprende una problemática evolutiva que alcanza y se instala en nuestro horizonte filosófico contemporáneo. Según Antonio Negri, las razones para afirmar la contemporaneidad de Spinoza no sólo son razones positivas, sino problemáticas. Hoy en día estas razones problemáticas hacen importante y valioso el estudio del pensamiento de Spinoza.

En The Savage Anomaly (University of Minnesota Press, Minneapolis, 1991), Negri inicia su análisis de la filosofía de Spinoza a partir de la idea que su metafísica representa la polaridad de una relación de fuerzas antagonistas: fuerzas y relaciones que experimentan una tendencia de contradicciones y conflictos. En este marco antagónico, la metafísica de Spinoza es la anomalía del materialismo, del ser que actúa y que, constituyéndose a sí mismo, plantea la posibilidad --ontológica y política-- de transformar el mundo, así como interrumpir la continuidad del tiempo homogéneo y milimetrado.

Ahora bien, siguiendo a Negri en su ensayo “Spinoza: Five Reasons for His Contemporaneity” (véase Subversive Spinoza, Manchester University Press, Manchester, 2004), he aquí las razones de la contemporaneidad de la filosofía de Spinoza:

Primera. Spinoza funda el materialismo moderno en su más alta expresión, es decir, determina el horizonte propio de la especulación filosófica moderna y contemporánea, que es el de una filosofía del ser inmanente como negación de todo orden previo a la constitución del ser y el obrar humano. El materialismo spinozista no supera, sin embargo, los límites de una concepción puramente “espacial” --galileiana-- del mundo. Spinoza intenta destruir los límites de tal concepción, pero no alcanza una solución, sino que deja irresoluto el problema de la relación entre las dimensiones espaciales y temporales del ser. La imaginación --esa facultad espiritual que recorre el sistema spinoziano—, aún en su forma más creativa y dinámica, constituye el ser en un orden que sólo es temporal.

Segunda. Spinoza describe el mundo como absoluta necesidad, como presencia de la necesidad. “Todas las cosas de la Naturaleza acontecen con cierta eterna necesidad”. (E1a) Pero esta misma presencia es contradictoria. Por un lado, restaura inmediatamente para nosotros la necesidad como contingencia, la absoluta necesidad como absoluta contingencia –dado que la absoluta contingencia es la única manera de afirmar el mundo como horizonte ético. Por el otro, el movimiento del ser expresado a través de las catástrofes del ser: lo que es, pero puede no ser; lo que es así, pero puede ser de otro modo. Se trata de la presencia del ser en los márgenes de la vida cotidiana y su necesidad dada como contingencia, tal es la paradoja de esta necesidad. Estamos en un orden de contingencia, y a esta contingencia le corresponde, precisamente, la libertad.

En Spinoza el sentido de las catástrofes del ser elimina todo determinismo hasta sus últimos vestigios. La necesidad del ser como conatus de ninguna manera sostiene el determinismo. Al contrario, es la absoluta contingencia. Sólo ahora podemos entender la completa significación del hecho que la necesidad es libertad. Abrazamos el mundo como libertad –este es el sentido de las catástrofes del ser que nos han sido restauradas como posibilidad de libertad y creación.

Así, Spinoza nos enseña a hacer una distinción en el mundo ético: la alternativa entre vida y muerte, entre construir o destruir. Cuando el poder ético se articula a sí mismo en la absoluta contingencia del ser, este movimiento se orienta necesariamente por las razones de la vida en contra de aquellas de la muerte. “El hombre libre en ninguna otra cosa piensa menos que en la muerte, y su sabiduría no es una meditación de la muerte, sino de la vida”. (E4p67) La acción ética será pues una acción de construcción en el corazón del ser --en tensión hacia lo singular y lo complejo. La radicalidad de la alternativa ilumina el drama e intensidad de la elección ética que se convierte en el pathos de la política: la imaginación creativa en oposición al orden de la muerte. “Los hombres libres se guían más por la esperanza que por el temor, mientras los hombres subyugados se guían más por el temor que por la esperanza; los primeros desean vivir, los últimos simplemente evitar la muerte”. (TP5,6)

Tercera. Spinoza describe la imaginación creativa como un poder ético, es decir, como la facultad que guía la construcción y el desarrollo de la libertad. Es la historia res gestae, la historia de la construcción y desarrollo de la libertad, y la articulación de su razón interna: naturalizar y racionalizar la acción humana. La razón que nos sitúa en la determinación radical de la elección ética: el esfuerzo (conatus) a perseverar en el ser. La ética descubre y reconoce la cualidad de la existencia humana, la tendencia a existir --ya sea hacia la vida o hacia la muerte--, como la determinación fundamental. Pero éstas no son sólo palabras, son seres, realidades ontológicas que desarrolla la imaginación creativa.

Spinoza excluye el tiempo-como-medida. Él aprehende el tiempo de la vida. El tiempo no es medida sino ética. Para Spinoza, el tiempo sólo existe como liberación. El tiempo liberado se convierte en imaginación creativa, en imaginación realizada. Pero el tiempo liberado no es devenir ni dialéctica, sino ser que se hace a sí mismo en la continua elección ética que fluya con el tiempo de la vida. La elección radical no es historia rerum gestarum (historia como conocimiento abstracto) sino historia res gestae (historia como saber vital), es decir, la afirmación de la necesidad de ser, del poder de ser. “Cada cosa, en cuanto está en ella [en cuanto es en sí], se esfuerza por perseverar en su ser”. (E3p6)

Cuarta. El concepto spinozista de amor y cuerpo. La expresión del ser comprende un gran acto sensual que comprende el cuerpo y la multiplicidad de cuerpos. Ser significa participar en la multiplicidad. “Lo que dispone al cuerpo humano de tal suerte que pueda ser afectado de muchísimos modos, o lo que lo vuelve apto para afectar los cuerpos externos de muchísimos modos, es útil para el hombre; y tanto más útil cuanto más apto vuelve al cuerpo para ser afectado y para afectar a los otros cuerpos de muchísimos modos; y, por el contrario, es nocivo lo que vuelve al cuerpo menos apto para eso”. (E4p38)

Para Spinoza, el ser es fuente de emanación, esto es, fuente de una realidad de la que emana otra realidad ad infinitum. Este nuevo ser se nos ofrece a través de mil y una acciones singulares de cada ser, es decir, cada uno de nosotros juega un papel en el desarrollo del ser. El amor estrecha seres diferentes; es un acto que une cuerpos y los multiplica, dándoles nacimiento y reproduciendo su esencia singular. Si no estuviéramos inmersos en esta comunidad amorosa de cuerpos, de átomos vivientes, nosotros no existiríamos. Así, nuestra existencia es siempre colectiva en sí misma. En contra del solipsismo y el individualismo está la superabundancia del ser que ha elevado la fuerza de los deseos más allá de toda medida. “El deseo [cupiditas] es la esencia misma del hombre, esto es, el esfuerzo con que el hombre se esfuerza por perseverar en su ser”. (E4p18d) El deseo es así el cimiento del amor y el ser.

Quinta. Otra razón de la contemporaneidad de Spinoza es el heroísmo de su carácter filosófico. Ni el coraje de Giordano Bruno ni el vértigo de Blas Pascal, sino la serena lucidez de Spinoza. Gilles Deleuze lo llama “el príncipe de los filósofos”. Es el heroísmo de la imaginación, de la acción y el deseo de libertad; el heroísmo del descubrimiento intelectual, que exige una lúcida fuerza de clarificación e imaginación teórica. En Spinoza, la resistencia y la dignidad, el rechazo de la agitación de una vida sin sentido, la independencia de la razón, no son preceptos morales, sino un teorema ético.

En suma, Spinoza pensó --parafraseando a Deleuze--, el afuera y el adentro del pensamiento, el afuera no exterior y el adentro no interior. Lo que no puede ser pensado y no obstante debe ser pensado. Spinoza no se entregó a la trascendencia, el devenir o la dialéctica, al contrario, mostró, estableció, pensó la posibilidad de lo imposible: el misterio del ser inmanente.

alm

04 noviembre, 2011

Simon Choat: Review of 'Second Manifesto for Philosophy' by Alain Badiou

Alain Badiou, Second Manifesto for Philosophy, trans. Louise Burchill, Polity, Cambridge, 2011, 176 pp.

This book is a sequel of sorts to Badiou’s Manifesto for Philosophy, which was first published in France in 1989. Both volumes offer a polemical defence of Badiou’s vision of philosophy and a summary of his latest thinking. The first Manifesto acted as an abridged version of Being and Event, whose arguments it presented in condensed form; the Second Manifesto does the same job for Badiou’s recent Logics of Worlds.

When the first Manifesto was translated into English in 1999, Badiou was still relatively unknown in the Anglophone world; today, he is firmly established within the canon of contemporary Continental philosophy, with more than a dozen of his books translated in the past five years. The explosion of interest in his work can at least in part be attributed to the fact that his ideas and arguments are genuinely novel. More than any other contemporary philosopher, Badiou has challenged the conventions of post-structuralist thought in all its forms, from Derridean deconstruction to Deleuzian metaphysics, resurrecting unfashionable concepts like truth and universalism and reclaiming thinkers long derided.

This critical attitude toward post-structuralism played an important role in the first Manifesto. The polemical force of that book was aimed at contemporary French Heideggerianism, specifically its assertion of the end or impasse of philosophy, its recourse to poetry and art, and its deconstruction of the subject. In contrast, Badiou insisted on the need to think the conditions under which philosophy is possible, desuturing it from those conditions (including art) and rethinking the subject. The target of the Second Manifesto is less carefully drawn, and a bit harder to identify. Badiou continues to oppose philosophy to sophism, but no longer that of the French Heideggerians. Today’s sophists are more mundane: they are those ‘democratic materialists’ who reject principles and truths in the name of fetishised notion of public opinion and a supposedly pragmatic managerialism. The threat to philosophy today, Badiou argues, comes not from deconstructive proclamations of the end of metaphysics and the reduction of philosophy to its conditions, but from philosophy’s over-inflation: philosophy (or rather what today passes for philosophy) finds itself everywhere, offered as fodder for TV shows and lifestyle magazines and called upon to act as the ethical conscience of big business and high finance. Indistinguishable from the mainstream moralising discourse of human rights, ‘philosophy’ today does nothing more than supplement our dominant ideology, reinforcing the values of capitalism and an unthinking scientism.

Badiou’s critique is thus much less focused this time around. The first Manifesto attacked a clearly delimited and readily identifiable set of thinkers. Alongside economic managerialism, human rights, and neuro-positivism, however, the Second Manifesto also manages to lambast cultural relativism, the nuclear family, American militarism, media punditry, and anti-Islamism. This scattergun polemic makes for a somewhat disjointed and uneven book. In the first Manifesto, the critique of his philosophical contemporaries was used to introduce and illuminate Badiou’s own philosophy: it was in opposition to the aestheticisation of philosophy and the dethroning of truth that Badiou was able to outline his own theory of philosophy as that which constructs a space for the reception of truths. In addition, criticism of Heideggerian diatribes on technology and nihilism gave Badiou the opportunity to delineate a powerful (albeit underdeveloped) account of the relation between philosophy and capitalism. In the Second Manifesto the link between criticism of others and clarification of his own philosophy is more tenuous: instead, we have a mocking condemnation of politicians, TV presenters, and other easy targets, followed by an exceptionally dense and demanding outline of Badiou’s latest philosophical explorations.

If this new book has a main enemy, it is those who deny that there are such things as truths. This continues Badiou’s previous work – but as he explains in his concluding chapter (which offers a useful summary of the distinctions between the first and second manifestoes), if the first Manifesto sought to establish the universality of truths (against all forms of cultural relativism), the Second Manifesto emphasises their eternality (128-9). How can truths that are created within one particular world possess value for very different worlds? How is it possible – to use Badiou’s example – that paintings daubed on a cave wall 40,000 years ago can still be understood and used by us today? As Badiou notes (23), Marx had his own answer to these kinds of questions: the famous claim made in the Grundrisse that we continue to enjoy Greek art because ancient Greece was the childhood of humanity, and everyone loves a child. Badiou dismisses Marx’s response, claiming that it is ‘as feeble as it is touching’ (and ‘also very German’) (23). Instead, we should acknowledge that there are artistic, scientific, political, and amorous truths that are eternally valid.

This shift of emphasis from universality to eternality entails another change of focus: if the first Manifesto established that there are universal truths, the Second Manifesto is interested in how truths appear and are sustained as bodies in the world. Granted that there is such a thing as a truth whose ‘significance is not exhausted by that which materially binds it to its world of appearance’ (27), how do these truths come to appear in our particular, material world? This question reflects and is part of a broader change in Badiou’s whole project. Whereas Being and Event offered a theory of being as pure multiplicity, Logics of Worlds (and hence also the Second Manifesto) examines beings as they appear – not as pure multiplicities but as differentiated from other beings. If the first Manifesto called for a radical ‘disobjectivation’ – declaring the need to think an objectless subject – the Second Manifesto restores the ‘object’ as a legitimate philosophical category: it aims to show how a being can appear as an object in a world. We have thus moved from ontology (i.e. the investigation of being as being) to phenomenology – by which Badiou means the investigation of ‘being-there’ (31), or the existence of objects in different worlds.

Badiou’s work has previously been criticised for its abstraction and lack of engagement with social, historical, and economic factors. Those hoping that his phenomenological turn will lead Badiou away from the often intimidating formalism of his earlier work are likely to be disappointed. As is well known, in Being and Event Badiou identifies ontology with mathematics. In Logics of Worlds and its companion manifesto, he identifies phenomenology with logic. For Badiou, phenomenology is about the forms of relation that objects enter into – and it is logic that offers us a ‘formal theory of relations’ (31). In common with most commentators on Badiou, at this point I am forced to confess my ignorance of recent developments in mathematics – though in some senses Badiou’s turn to logic should be less daunting than his earlier use of set theory: logic, after all, is a well-established branch of philosophy, pursued by some of its most notable practitioners (Aristotle, Hegel, Mill, etc.). Nonetheless, given that his arguments can be expressed and understood without their mathematical framework, it remains difficult to shake off suspicions about the use that Badiou makes of mathematics, apart from its role in drawing on the intellectual authority that has traditionally been awarded to the hard sciences.

If ontology is interested only in the being of a multiplicity, ‘divested of all the qualitative predicates which make of it a singular thing’ (28), then Badiou’s phenomenology investigates the qualities of multiplicities insofar as they appear as objects differentiated from other objects: it is interested in the ‘degrees of identity’ between multiplicities, or in other words the extent to which two things appear similar or different. Any world (and there are many) is governed by a ‘transcendental’ that organises these degrees of identity. For example, in the world of a preoccupied commuter, two ants on the floor may appear basically identical – the degree of identity will be very strong – whereas in the world of an entomologist the two insects may appear very different to each other, and the ‘degree of identity’ will therefore be much weaker. ‘Existence’ is defined by Badiou as ‘the measure of an identity of a thing to itself’: it is ‘a transcendental degree indicating the intensity of a multiplicity’s appearing in a given world’ (57-8). What this means is that things can exist in the world to different degrees, and there can even be things that are in the world but are inexistent. Indeed, Badiou claims that ‘if a multiplicity appears in a world, one element of this multiplicity, and one alone, is an inexistent of the world.’ (60) Badiou’s example is inspired by Marx: in bourgeois society, the proletariat does not exist; it ‘can be analysed but, according to the rules [or transcendental] governing the appearance of the political world, it does not appear within this.’ (61) For the inexistent to appear, there must be a disruption of the transcendental: ‘a perturbation of the world’s order’ (91). A suitably radical change is named an event, which gives rise to a truth process as ‘the construction of a new body’ (90).

From a Marxist perspective, the concept of the transcendental as a world’s ‘structural order’ (53) does raise a series of questions. Where does the transcendental come from? Whose interests does it serve? How is it sustained? And, perhaps most importantly, how can it be challenged and overturned? Granted that it is desirable that (for example) the proletariat are raised from inexistence to maximal existence, how is this to happen? How will change come about? Badiou’s previous account of radical change was frequently criticised: it seemed as if the event’ just appeared from nowhere, as if falling from the sky. His new conceptual arsenal does allow for a more subtle approach. Events are now distinguished more thoroughly from other forms of change, and in theory the concept of the transcendental as the system of rules governing a world means that the conditions of events can be analysed, though it remains to be seen how useful these concepts are for the analysis of social forms. The relation between truth and subject is also now more subtle. In earlier works, the ‘subject’ referred to that individual or collective who sustained a truth by being faithful to an event. Badiou now acknowledges that there can be other types of subject – not only faithful but also ‘reactive’ (maintaining that the world should carry on as normal) and ‘obscure’ (calling for the liquidation of the faithful subject and the destruction of the new truth) (92-5). But there is still no sense that a subject might be something that takes part in or causes events: in a sense the subject is always ‘reactive’ for Badiou, because it is only ever a reaction to an event. In addition, despite Badiou’s polemicising, he never exorcises the spectre of relativism: if truths are sustained by subjects, then what are we left with other than a radical decisionism? The alternative that Badiou offers in his conclusion – ‘either war-mongering capitalist parliamentarianism ... or the victorious renewal of the Communist hypothesis’ (124) – is admirably clear, but it remains in doubt how useful his own philosophy is for elucidating and responding to this alternative.

I have only been able to touch on some of this book’s themes here – but then that is all Badiou is able to do in such a short volume: the attempt to condense the massive Logics of Worlds into a small manifesto means that we end up with a book that is often exceedingly dense and difficult. But, then, given Badiou’s views on philosophy, it would be absurd to complain that this book is not easy enough. If this Second Manifesto does not reach the heights of the first, then that is to be expected, given that the first Manifesto is one of Badiou’s finest books (and, along with his Ethics, probably the best introduction to his unique philosophy). And if readers of this book are forced to turn to Logics of Worlds to make sense of some of the more obscure passages, then in a sense it means that this manifesto has done its job as an appetizer for Badiou’s current thinking.

Source: Marx & Philosophy Review of Books